MacIntyre on the Is-Ought Problem

6 comments
In a previous post, I introduced the so-called "Is/Ought Problem," first made famous by David Hume.  Hume argued that you cannot get from an "is" to an "ought"-- that is, you cannot argue from the way that things currently are, to the way that things ought to be.  Or more generally, you cannot get from factual statements to evaluative statements.  But this is exactly how many people argue in a moral context-- "punching someone causes them pain, therefore you should not punch someone," for example. Or "James is fast and strong. He should play football." But is this true?  Is it always uncalled for to argue from premises involving the way things are, to conclusions involving the way things ought to be?


In After Virtue, Alasdair MacIntyre gives several counter-examples for why this is not the case.  Consider first:
There are several types of valid argument in which some element may appear in a conclusion which is not present in the premises. A.N. Prior's counter-example to this alleged principle illustrates its breakdown adequately; from the premise 'He is a sea-captain', the conclusion may be validly inferred that 'He ought to do whatever a sea-captain ought to do'. This counter-example not only shows that there is no general principle of the type alleged; but it itself shows what is at least a grammatical truth - an 'is' premise can on occasion entail an 'ought' conclusion. [1]
You can see here that the reason this example succeeds is because there is a concept of "Sea Captain" which entails certain responsibilities.  Those responsibilities are built into what it means to be a sea captain.  Thus the counter-example adequately shows why Hume's contention is wrong, at least in some cases.  Consider further:
From such factual premises as 'This watch is grossly inaccurate and irregular in time-keeping' and 'This watch is too heavy to carry about comfortably', the evaluative conclusion validly follows that 'This is a bad watch'. From such factual premises as 'He gets a better yield for this crop per acre than any farmer in the district', 'He has the most effective programme of soil renewal yet known' and 'His dairy herd wins all the first prizes at the agricultural shows', the evaluative conclusion validly follows that 'He is a good farmer'.  
Both of these arguments are valid because of the special character of the concepts of a watch and of a farmer. Such concepts are functional concepts; that is to say, we define both 'watch' and 'farmer' in terms of the purpose or function which a watch or a farmer are characteristically expected to serve. It follows that the concept of a watch cannot be defined independently of the concept of a good watch nor the concept of a farmer independently of that of a good farmer; and that the criterion of something's being a watch and the criterion of something's being a good watch-- and so also for 'farmer' and for all other functional concepts-- are not independent of each other. [...]  
Now clearly both sets of criteria-- as is evidenced by the examples given in the last paragraph-- are factual. Hence any argument which moves from premises which assert that the appropriate criteria are satisfied to a conclusion which asserts that 'That is a good such-and-such', where 'such-and-such' picks out an item specified by a functional concept, will be a valid argument which moves from factual premises to an evaluative conclusion. Thus we may safely assert that, if some amended version of the 'No "ought" conclusion from "is" premises' principle is to hold good, it must exclude arguments involving functional concepts from its scope. But this suggests strongly that those who have insisted that all moral arguments fall within the scope of such a principle may have been doing so, because they took it for granted that no moral arguments involve functional concepts. [2]
So we have two examples of arguments which start from premises stating only the way things are, to a conclusion that entails some evaluative judgement.  MacIntyre rightly points out that at this point Hume's defenders can only proceed by modifying their principle.  Perhaps it is the case that evaluative conclusion can (in some cases) proceed from factual premises.  Perhaps instead, the principle is only true from those arguments which do not involve functional concepts.  But this shift identifies and magnifies the breakdown of the Enlightenment attempt to justify morality rationally, a major thesis of MacIntyre's book:

Yet moral arguments within the classical, Aristotelian tradition-- whether in its Greek or its medieval versions-- involve at least one central functional concept, the concept of man understood as having an essential nature and an essential purpose or function; and it is when and only when the classical tradition in its integrity has been substantially rejected that moral arguments change their character so that they fall within the scope of some version of the 'No "ought" conclusion from "is" premises' principle. That is to say, 'man' stands to 'good man' as 'watch' stands to 'good watch' or 'farmer' to 'good farmer' within the classical tradition. Aristotle takes it as a starting-point for ethical enquiry that the relationship of 'man' to 'living well' is analogous to that of 'harpist' to 'playing the harp well' (Nicomachean Ethics, 1095a 16). But the use of 'man' as a functional concept is far older than Aristotle and it does not initially derive from Aristotle's metaphysical biology. It is rooted in the forms of social life to which the theorists of the classical tradition give expression. For according to that tradition to be a man is to fill a set of roles each of which has its own point and purpose: member of a family , citizen, soldier, philosopher, servant of God. It is only when man is thought of as an individual prior to and apart from all roles that 'man' ceases to be a functional concept. [3]
Thus the failure involves not a simple disagreement with classical thinkers (the predecessor culture, as MacIntyre calls it), but a wholesale rejection of the classical worldview, whereby "man" was understood to have an essential nature.  And this essential nature involves functional concepts.  To say a man is a "good man" is no different from saying a watch is a "good watch," a farmer is a "good farmer," or a sea-captain is a "good sea-captain" on the classical view.  Each of these is true in virtue of the role that they play, and the functionality which they essentially exhibit. 

So given Hume's presuppositions (a complete rejection of the classical worldview, especially the idea of man's essential nature and telos), he may have been right that morally evaluative conclusions could not be derived from factual premises.  However, these presuppositions (shared by many Enlightenment and post-Enlightenment thinkers) are not obviously true.


Notes:
1. MacIntyre, 1981, p.57
2. Ibid. pp.57-58
3. Ibid. pp.58-59
Next Post Newer Post Previous Post Older Post Home

6 comments :

  1. Great post thank you for that.

    Is it not just a tautology if we simply define sea captain as including " one who ought to do the best for the ship"?

    In that case, we have not really gotten from "is" to "ought", but merely from "x" to "x".

    ReplyDelete
  2. Thanks for your kind words Steve.

    It is a tautology in the sense that all deductive inferences are tautological-- the conclusion is already contained in the premises. For a deductive inference, we are not learning anything new that was already present. Consider an arbitrary example of a deductive inference:

    1) All massive objects have inertia.
    2) Austin is a massive object.
    3) Therefore, Austin has inertia.

    The conclusion (3) is already contained in the premises (1) and (2). We aren't providing novel information in (3), we are simply making explicit what was already implicit in (1) and (2). But that doesn't make (3) any less significant!

    In MacIntyre's example (which was first Prior's) we are doing a similar thing. We are going from an 'is' to an 'ought.' It's just that the 'ought' is sort of already contained in the 'is,' and what we're doing is essentially drawing it out.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. I should note for clarification that the entire controversy regarding morality revolves around my last sentence in the comment: "It's just that the 'ought' is sort of already contained in the 'is.' " Hume, and most modern philosophers, reject the classical view whereby man has an essential nature and telos. So for modern philosophers, there is no "ought" contained in the "is" of "Austin is a man," etc.

      Delete
    2. How would we reply to someone who denies the relationship between "man" and "living well"?

      Is it a first principle of some sorts?

      I am just not sure that McIntyre successfully avoids the ultimately contingent nature of moral discourse.

      Delete
    3. There isn't a simple response that MacIntyre would give to that question. Probably a third of the book is dedicated to showing how pre-moderns accepted that relationship, and moderns do not. The relationship is dependent on an understanding of humans as having an essential nature in a non-reductionist sense, and telos being a part of that. Ultimately, it seems like MacIntyre would admit that this is a difference in two different traditions (pre-modern and modern) that is more or less incommensurable. In this sense there's no way he could prove the modern understanding of that relationship to be wrong from either within his own tradition, or from some objective external standpoint.

      What he would attempt to do is show that the modern conceptions of morality have too many problems even from within their own tradition, and are doomed to continue failing without the acceptance of man as having an essential nature. But this gets into his epistemology which is another whole animal.

      The point of this post, and the portions quoted from the book, isn't necessarily to argue that this is the correct conception of morality (that is done elsewhere). Rather it is to show that evaluative conclusions can be drawn from factual premises, provided that those factual premises entail some sort of functional concepts.

      Delete
  3. Hume said you cannot derive a conclusion containing an ought from premises that do not contain an ought. The sea-captain argument is presented as the derivation of a conclusion from only one premise. There is a hidden premise which is not stated, to wit, "a sea-captain ought to behave in such-and-such ways". Without this hidden premise it would be possible for me to deny that a sea-captain ought to behave like a sea-captain, and there would be no logical refutation. I think Prior's argument is childish sophistry.

    ReplyDelete